Human Nature Essay, Research Paper
Our life is full of problems. Reasoning is a usual way to response to problems which we concern about. We reason in response to everyday problems. For instance, asked by friends to go out dinner at a time when we have planned something else, we must decide which one is more important for us at that moment of time, and whether to decline or to adjust our schedule. Reasoning appropriate to problems like this has often been called practical. Practical reasons might be said to be reasons for acting, and it is in some sense point toward action. Practical reasoning has been much discussed by philosophers, and it is catalogued under Moral Philosophy. For Aristotle s moral philosophy, as it appears in his document now called the Nicomachean ethics, reflects his teleological (goal-oriented) metaphyics. In the Nicomachean ethics, where Aristotle considers a science of doing, and acting in certain way to seek rational ends. The notion of Goal, or Purpose, is the principal one in his moral theory.
Aristotle noted that every act is performed for some purpose, which he defined as the “good” of that act, the end at which the activity aims. We perform an act because we find its purpose to be worthwhile. Either the totality of our acts is an infinitely circular series: Every morning we get up in order to eat breakfast, we eat breakfast in order to go to work, we got to work in order to get money, we get money so we can buy food in order to be able to eat breakfast, etc., etc., etc., in which case life would be a pretty meaningless endeavor because this is just bunch of repeated and vain activities practicing if without a purpose. Or there is some ultimate good toward which the purpose of all acts are directed. If there is such a good, we should try to come to know it so that we can adjust all our acts toward it in order to avoid that saddest of all tragedies the wasted and vain life
According to Aristotle, there is general verbal agreement that the end toward which all human acts are directed is happiness; therefore, happiness is the human good since we seek happiness for its own sake, not for the sake of something else. In a sense, realizing the end of attaining happiness is an activity of making, and it s the activity aims to make a certain kind of man, living in a certain kind of society. Happiness might be explained as the fruition of a man s way of life, in the truly human aspect of that way of life. The good of each thing is its own function; thus, vision is the good of the eye and walking is the good of the foot. As Aristotle said in the Nicomachean ethics, “Every art and every inquiry, and similarly every action and pursuit, is thought to aim at some good; and for this reason the good has rightly been declared to be that at which all things aim.” (11) However, unless we philosophize about happiness and get to know exactly what it is and how to achieve it, it will be stereotyped simply to say that happiness is the ultimate good. To determine the nature of happiness, Aristotle turned to his metaphysical schema and asked, “What is the function of the human?” In the same way he would ask about the function of a knife or a cloth. He came to the conclusion that a human s function is to engage in “an activity of the soul which is in accordance with virtue and which follows a rational principle.” Before grasping this complicated definition , we must determine what virtues is and what kinds of virtues there are. But first, we must have a basic understanding that Aristotle believed that certain material conditions must hold before happiness can be achieved.
This list of conditions will show Aristotle s elitism: We need good friends, riches, and political power. We need a good birth, good children, and good looks. For the man who is very ugly in appearance is not likely to be happy. Also we must not be very short. Furthermore, we must be free from the need of performing manual labor. According to Aristotle, no man can practice virtue who is living the life of a mechanic or laborer. Personally, I am strongly disagree on these conditions which Aristotle had claimed as the criteria toward Happiness. There should not have a set of conditions or definitions on Happiness because different people have different ways of understand happiness, and different people have different beliefs and goals toward their own life. It should be noted that Aristotle s moral theory would be left substantially perfect if his elitist bias were deleted.
Now, as to virtues, there are two kinds: Intellectual and moral, corresponding to the two parts of the soul. Intellectual virtues are acquired through a combination of inheritance and education, and moral virtues through imitation, practice, and habit. The habits that we develop result in “states of character,” that is , in dispositions to act certain ways, and these states of character are “virtuous” for Aristotle if they result in acts that are in accordance with a “golden mean” of moderation. Courage is a mean between cowardice and foolhardiness. For example, when it comes to facing danger, one can act with excess, that is, show too much fear. (This is cowardice.) Or one can act deficiently by showing too little fear. (This is foolhardiness.) Or one can act with moderation, and hence virtuously, by showing the right amount of fear. (This is courage.) Aristotle realized that the choices we must make if we are to learn moral virtue cannot be made mathematically; rather, they are always context-bound and must be approached through trial and error.
Returning to the intellectual virtues of practical and philosophical wisdom, the former is the wisdom necessary to make judgments consistent with one s understanding of the good life. It is therefore related to moral virtue. Philosophical wisdom is scientific, disinterested, and contemplative. It is associated with pure reason, and, for Aristotle, the capacity for reason is that which is most human; therefore, philosophical wisdom is the highest virtue. So, when Aristotle defined happiness as “an activity of the soul in accordance with virtue,” the activity referred to is philosophical activity. The human being can only be happy by leading a contemplative life, but not a monastic one. We are not only philosophical animals but also social ones. We are engaged in a would where decisions concerning practical matters are forced upon us constantly. Happiness (hence the good life) requires excellence in both spheres. Therefore, in the Aristotelian view, that the highest virtue is for the few. In the Nicomachean Ethics, Aristotle argues that the function of man is an activity of soul which follows a rational principle which based on both virtues.
Human good turns out to be activity of soul in accordance with virtue, and if there are more than one virtue, in accordance with the best and most complete. But we must add “in a complete life.” For one swallow does not make a summer, nor does on day; and so too one day, or a short time, does not make a man blessed and happy.
One who is trying to live according to a rational principle as what Aristotle suggested, aiming for happiness, will surely find that such a life is very difficult, that the swallows do not long remain, that the happy days do not last. What we try to do, in living out our days of contested moral positions, is to seek happiness. But usually what we find is very little happiness and very much despair, especially in the long run, “in a complete life.” Aristotle s end A happy man in a complete life seems unrealistic.
As mentioned before, different people might hold different belief toward happiness.
Belief is that upon which a man is prepared to act. Beliefs, then, are rules of action, and they got their meaning from the action for which they are rules. Beliefs produced habits, and that the way to distinguish between beliefs was to compare the habits they produced. A person s belief could be established by observing that person s actions If certain people believed that God existed, they would conceive of the world very differently from the way they would conceive of it if they believed God did not exist. Also, their definition toward happiness would also be very different from those who do not believe in God. However, there are other people whose conceptions of the world would be practically identical whether they believed that God did or did not exist. For certain other people who find themselves somewhere between these two extremes, the proposition “God exists” means something like this: “On Sunday, I put on nice clothes and go to church.” This is because, for them, engaging in this activity is the only practical outcome of their belief. For those who are Christian, richness might not have so much meaning to them. It is because their definition on happiness is not depend on how rich you are, and this is exactly why I opposed Aristotle s elitism.
Clearly, practical reasoning which Aristotle founded it provides a way to understand and explain actions. There are two important points with this founding. First, the method is reasoning in the context of a desired end, at least typically in a way that includes a commitment to some principle or belief. This provides motivation for the action issuing from the reasoning. Second, this provides guidance for the action. It is exercised in part by a belief to the effect that the end can be achieved by a certain kind of action, for instance, in order for reaching a sweet, one might go buy some candy. The belief helps to sustain and guide the action.
In conclude, Happiness is not a further end of the action, but its essential end. To act for a reason is to act in order to achieve an end, whether ultimate or, more often, subsidiary, as when we prescribe medicine in order to cure. Actions performed for a reason very commonly issue from practical reasoning; and if Aristotle does not think they always do, he at least holds that they are motivationally attached by a purposive chain which terminates in a desire for happiness and can be associated, link by link, with practical arguments that concern the relevant want, belief, and action, or at least of all action performed for a reason, is behavioral foundationalism.
Our life is full of problems. Reasoning is a usual way to response to problems which we concern about. We reason in response to everyday problems. For instance, asked by friends to go out dinner at a time when we have planned something else, we must decide which one is more important for us at that moment of time, and whether to decline or to adjust our schedule. Reasoning appropriate to problems like this has often been called practical. Practical reasons might be said to be reasons for acting, and it is in some sense point toward action. Practical reasoning has been much discussed by philosophers, and it is catalogued under Moral Philosophy. For Aristotle s moral philosophy, as it appears in his document now called the Nicomachean ethics, reflects his teleological (goal-oriented) metaphyics. In the Nicomachean ethics, where Aristotle considers a science of doing, and acting in certain way to seek rational ends. The notion of Goal, or Purpose, is the principal one in his moral theory.
Aristotle noted that every act is performed for some purpose, which he defined as the “good” of that act, the end at which the activity aims. We perform an act because we find its purpose to be worthwhile. Either the totality of our acts is an infinitely circular series: Every morning we get up in order to eat breakfast, we eat breakfast in order to go to work, we got to work in order to get money, we get money so we can buy food in order to be able to eat breakfast, etc., etc., etc., in which case life would be a pretty meaningless endeavor because this is just bunch of repeated and vain activities practicing if without a purpose. Or there is some ultimate good toward which the purpose of all acts are directed. If there is such a good, we should try to come to know it so that we can adjust all our acts toward it in order to avoid that saddest of all tragedies the wasted and vain life
According to Aristotle, there is general verbal agreement that the end toward which all human acts are directed is happiness; therefore, happiness is the human good since we seek happiness for its own sake, not for the sake of something else. In a sense, realizing the end of attaining happiness is an activity of making, and it s the activity aims to make a certain kind of man, living in a certain kind of society. Happiness might be explained as the fruition of a man s way of life, in the truly human aspect of that way of life. The good of each thing is its own function; thus, vision is the good of the eye and walking is the good of the foot. As Aristotle said in the Nicomachean ethics, “Every art and every inquiry, and similarly every action and pursuit, is thought to aim at some good; and for this reason the good has rightly been declared to be that at which all things aim.” (11) However, unless we philosophize about happiness and get to know exactly what it is and how to achieve it, it will be stereotyped simply to say that happiness is the ultimate good. To determine the nature of happiness, Aristotle turned to his metaphysical schema and asked, “What is the function of the human?” In the same way he would ask about the function of a knife or a cloth. He came to the conclusion that a human s function is to engage in “an activity of the soul which is in accordance with virtue and which follows a rational principle.” Before grasping this complicated definition , we must determine what virtues is and what kinds of virtues there are. But first, we must have a basic understanding that Aristotle believed that certain material conditions must hold before happiness can be achieved.
This list of conditions will show Aristotle s elitism: We need good friends, riches, and political power. We need a good birth, good children, and good looks. For the man who is very ugly in appearance is not likely to be happy. Also we must not be very short. Furthermore, we must be free from the need of performing manual labor. According to Aristotle, no man can practice virtue who is living the life of a mechanic or laborer. Personally, I am strongly disagree on these conditions which Aristotle had claimed as the criteria toward Happiness. There should not have a set of conditions or definitions on Happiness because different people have different ways of understand happiness, and different people have different beliefs and goals toward their own life. It should be noted that Aristotle s moral theory would be left substantially perfect if his elitist bias were deleted.
Now, as to virtues, there are two kinds: Intellectual and moral, corresponding to the two parts of the soul. Intellectual virtues are acquired through a combination of inheritance and education, and moral virtues through imitation, practice, and habit. The habits that we develop result in “states of character,” that is , in dispositions to act certain ways, and these states of character are “virtuous” for Aristotle if they result in acts that are in accordance with a “golden mean” of moderation. Courage is a mean between cowardice and foolhardiness. For example, when it comes to facing danger, one can act with excess, that is, show too much fear. (This is cowardice.) Or one can act deficiently by showing too little fear. (This is foolhardiness.) Or one can act with moderation, and hence virtuously, by showing the right amount of fear. (This is courage.) Aristotle realized that the choices we must make if we are to learn moral virtue cannot be made mathematically; rather, they are always context-bound and must be approached through trial and error.
Returning to the intellectual virtues of practical and philosophical wisdom, the former is the wisdom necessary to make judgments consistent with one s understanding of the good life. It is therefore related to moral virtue. Philosophical wisdom is scientific, disinterested, and contemplative. It is associated with pure reason, and, for Aristotle, the capacity for reason is that which is most human; therefore, philosophical wisdom is the highest virtue. So, when Aristotle defined happiness as “an activity of the soul in accordance with virtue,” the activity referred to is philosophical activity. The human being can only be happy by leading a contemplative life, but not a monastic one. We are not only philosophical animals but also social ones. We are engaged in a would where decisions concerning practical matters are forced upon us constantly. Happiness (hence the good life) requires excellence in both spheres. Therefore, in the Aristotelian view, that the highest virtue is for the few. In the Nicomachean Ethics, Aristotle argues that the function of man is an activity of soul which follows a rational principle which based on both virtues.
Human good turns out to be activity of soul in accordance with virtue, and if there are more than one virtue, in accordance with the best and most complete. But we must add “in a complete life.” For one swallow does not make a summer, nor does on day; and so too one day, or a short time, does not make a man blessed and happy.
One who is trying to live according to a rational principle as what Aristotle suggested, aiming for happiness, will surely find that such a life is very difficult, that the swallows do not long remain, that the happy days do not last. What we try to do, in living out our days of contested moral positions, is to seek happiness. But usually what we find is very little happiness and very much despair, especially in the long run, “in a complete life.” Aristotle s end A happy man in a complete life seems unrealistic.
As mentioned before, different people might hold different belief toward happiness.
Belief is that upon which a man is prepared to act. Beliefs, then, are rules of action, and they got their meaning from the action for which they are rules. Beliefs produced habits, and that the way to distinguish between beliefs was to compare the habits they produced. A person s belief could be established by observing that person s actions If certain people believed that God existed, they would conceive of the world very differently from the way they would conceive of it if they believed God did not exist. Also, their definition toward happiness would also be very different from those who do not believe in God. However, there are other people whose conceptions of the world would be practically identical whether they believed that God did or did not exist. For certain other people who find themselves somewhere between these two extremes, the proposition “God exists” means something like this: “On Sunday, I put on nice clothes and go to church.” This is because, for them, engaging in this activity is the only practical outcome of their belief. For those who are Christian, richness might not have so much meaning to them. It is because their definition on happiness is not depend on how rich you are, and this is exactly why I opposed Aristotle s elitism.
Clearly, practical reasoning which Aristotle founded it provides a way to understand and explain actions. There are two important points with this founding. First, the method is reasoning in the context of a desired end, at least typically in a way that includes a commitment to some principle or belief. This provides motivation for the action issuing from the reasoning. Second, this provides guidance for the action. It is exercised in part by a belief to the effect that the end can be achieved by a certain kind of action, for instance, in order for reaching a sweet, one might go buy some candy. The belief helps to sustain and guide the action.
In conclude, Happiness is not a further end of the action, but its essential end. To act for a reason is to act in order to achieve an end, whether ultimate or, more often, subsidiary, as when we prescribe medicine in order to cure. Actions performed for a reason very commonly issue from practical reasoning; and if Aristotle does not think they always do, he at least holds that they are motivationally attached by a purposive chain which terminates in a desire for happiness and can be associated, link by link, with practical arguments that concern the relevant want, belief, and action, or at least of all action performed for a reason, is behavioral foundationalism.
Our life is full of problems. Reasoning is a usual way to response to problems which we concern about. We reason in response to everyday problems. For instance, asked by friends to go out dinner at a time when we have planned something else, we must decide which one is more important for us at that moment of time, and whether to decline or to adjust our schedule. Reasoning appropriate to problems like this has often been called practical. Practical reasons might be said to be reasons for acting, and it is in some sense point toward action. Practical reasoning has been much discussed by philosophers, and it is catalogued under Moral Philosophy. For Aristotle s moral philosophy, as it appears in his document now called the Nicomachean ethics, reflects his teleological (goal-oriented) metaphyics. In the Nicomachean ethics, where Aristotle considers a science of doing, and acting in certain way to seek rational ends. The notion of Goal, or Purpose, is the principal one in his moral theory.
Aristotle noted that every act is performed for some purpose, which he defined as the “good” of that act, the end at which the activity aims. We perform an act because we find its purpose to be worthwhile. Either the totality of our acts is an infinitely circular series: Every morning we get up in order to eat breakfast, we eat breakfast in order to go to work, we got to work in order to get money, we get money so we can buy food in order to be able to eat breakfast, etc., etc., etc., in which case life would be a pretty meaningless endeavor because this is just bunch of repeated and vain activities practicing if without a purpose. Or there is some ultimate good toward which the purpose of all acts are directed. If there is such a good, we should try to come to know it so that we can adjust all our acts toward it in order to avoid that saddest of all tragedies the wasted and vain life
According to Aristotle, there is general verbal agreement that the end toward which all human acts are directed is happiness; therefore, happiness is the human good since we seek happiness for its own sake, not for the sake of something else. In a sense, realizing the end of attaining happiness is an activity of making, and it s the activity aims to make a certain kind of man, living in a certain kind of society. Happiness might be explained as the fruition of a man s way of life, in the truly human aspect of that way of life. The good of each thing is its own function; thus, vision is the good of the eye and walking is the good of the foot. As Aristotle said in the Nicomachean ethics, “Every art and every inquiry, and similarly every action and pursuit, is thought to aim at some good; and for this reason the good has rightly been declared to be that at which all things aim.” (11) However, unless we philosophize about happiness and get to know exactly what it is and how to achieve it, it will be stereotyped simply to say that happiness is the ultimate good. To determine the nature of happiness, Aristotle turned to his metaphysical schema and asked, “What is the function of the human?” In the same way he would ask about the function of a knife or a cloth. He came to the conclusion that a human s function is to engage in “an activity of the soul which is in accordance with virtue and which follows a rational principle.” Before grasping this complicated definition , we must determine what virtues is and what kinds of virtues there are. But first, we must have a basic understanding that Aristotle believed that certain material conditions must hold before happiness can be achieved.
This list of conditions will show Aristotle s elitism: We need good friends, riches, and political power. We need a good birth, good children, and good looks. For the man who is very ugly in appearance is not likely to be happy. Also we must not be very short. Furthermore, we must be free from the need of performing manual labor. According to Aristotle, no man can practice virtue who is living the life of a mechanic or laborer. Personally, I am strongly disagree on these conditions which Aristotle had claimed as the criteria toward Happiness. There should not have a set of conditions or definitions on Happiness because different people have different ways of understand happiness, and different people have different beliefs and goals toward their own life. It should be noted that Aristotle s moral theory would be left substantially perfect if his elitist bias were deleted.
Now, as to virtues, there are two kinds: Intellectual and moral, corresponding to the two parts of the soul. Intellectual virtues are acquired through a combination of inheritance and education, and moral virtues through imitation, practice, and habit. The habits that we develop result in “states of character,” that is , in dispositions to act certain ways, and these states of character are “virtuous” for Aristotle if they result in acts that are in accordance with a “golden mean” of moderation. Courage is a mean between cowardice and foolhardiness. For example, when it comes to facing danger, one can act with excess, that is, show too much fear. (This is cowardice.) Or one can act deficiently by showing too little fear. (This is foolhardiness.) Or one can act with moderation, and hence virtuously, by showing the right amount of fear. (This is courage.) Aristotle realized that the choices we must make if we are to learn moral virtue cannot be made mathematically; rather, they are always context-bound and must be approached through trial and error.
Returning to the intellectual virtues of practical and philosophical wisdom, the former is the wisdom necessary to make judgments consistent with one s understanding of the good life. It is therefore related to moral virtue. Philosophical wisdom is scientific, disinterested, and contemplative. It is associated with pure reason, and, for Aristotle, the capacity for reason is that which is most human; therefore, philosophical wisdom is the highest virtue. So, when Aristotle defined happiness as “an activity of the soul in accordance with virtue,” the activity referred to is philosophical activity. The human being can only be happy by leading a contemplative life, but not a monastic one. We are not only philosophical animals but also social ones. We are engaged in a would where decisions concerning practical matters are forced upon us constantly. Happiness (hence the good life) requires excellence in both spheres. Therefore, in the Aristotelian view, that the highest virtue is for the few. In the Nicomachean Ethics, Aristotle argues that the function of man is an activity of soul which follows a rational principle which based on both virtues.
Human good turns out to be activity of soul in accordance with virtue, and if there are more than one virtue, in accordance with the best and most complete. But we must add “in a complete life.” For one swallow does not make a summer, nor does on day; and so too one day, or a short time, does not make a man blessed and happy.
One who is trying to live according to a rational principle as what Aristotle suggested, aiming for happiness, will surely find that such a life is very difficult, that the swallows do not long remain, that the happy days do not last. What we try to do, in living out our days of contested moral positions, is to seek happiness. But usually what we find is very little happiness and very much despair, especially in the long run, “in a complete life.” Aristotle s end A happy man in a complete life seems unrealistic.
As mentioned before, different people might hold different belief toward happiness.
Belief is that upon which a man is prepared to act. Beliefs, then, are rules of action, and they got their meaning from the action for which they are rules. Beliefs produced habits, and that the way to distinguish between beliefs was to compare the habits they produced. A person s belief could be established by observing that person s actions If certain people believed that God existed, they would conceive of the world very differently from the way they would conceive of it if they believed God did not exist. Also, their definition toward happiness would also be very different from those who do not believe in God. However, there are other people whose conceptions of the world would be practically identical whether they believed that God did or did not exist. For certain other people who find themselves somewhere between these two extremes, the proposition “God exists” means something like this: “On Sunday, I put on nice clothes and go to church.” This is because, for them, engaging in this activity is the only practical outcome of their belief. For those who are Christian, richness might not have so much meaning to them. It is because their definition on happiness is not depend on how rich you are, and this is exactly why I opposed Aristotle s elitism.
Clearly, practical reasoning which Aristotle founded it provides a way to understand and explain actions. There are two important points with this founding. First, the method is reasoning in the context of a d
! |
Как писать рефераты Практические рекомендации по написанию студенческих рефератов. |
! | План реферата Краткий список разделов, отражающий структура и порядок работы над будующим рефератом. |
! | Введение реферата Вводная часть работы, в которой отражается цель и обозначается список задач. |
! | Заключение реферата В заключении подводятся итоги, описывается была ли достигнута поставленная цель, каковы результаты. |
! | Оформление рефератов Методические рекомендации по грамотному оформлению работы по ГОСТ. |
→ | Виды рефератов Какими бывают рефераты по своему назначению и структуре. |